Miscellaneous fragments, mostly on pluralism
Henry Hardy
Pluralism, moral universals and
fullness of life
Pluralism entails a degree of
toleration, namely, enough freedom from direction and interference to
enable men to choose their own path. But it does not imply or involve
the relinquishing of universal moral standards; nor does it require or
allow us to confine ourselves to those values that can be seen as
universal. Indeed, the small core of shared values are arguably
insufficient to ground a fully-fledged moral life; one might even say
that there was a universal need to fill out the core with a
non-universal periphery: that a fully developed conception of life will
always contain both universal and non-universal components.
Pluralism, the limits
of variety, and religion
Pluralism recognises the legitimacy of variety in
conceptions of life; indeed it may encourage such variety as comprising
a rich moral ecology, much as the variety of biological species can be
encouraged on literally ecological grounds. But the variety it
recognises cannot be limitless, in two ways. First, shared human values
require any proffered conception of life to fall within certain limits
of acceptable human behaviour. Secondly, pluralism cannot consistently
accept conceptions of life that insist that moral variety is
illegitimate: in short, monism and pluralism are logically incompatible.
This last point can be most vividly illustrated by the phenomenon of
universalist religious creeds.[1]
Any religion which claims to preach a
comprehensive set of truths valid for all men, everywhere, is plainly
at odds with pluralism. Of course, some of the truths it preaches may
be part of the common moral core, but it is not on those grounds that
they are preached: the authority of religion is supposed to derive
primarily not
from empirical observation but from revelation. Notoriously,
revelations differ, quite apart from the problems inherent in
validating any particular instance of revelation. This creates acute
difficulties for those who seek to understand how the competing
revelations may be jointly understood if they are not all (or all but
one) to be rejected, but it also illustrates starkly how the variety of
religious dispensations differs from the variety of approaches to life
sponsored by pluralism. The various views of life that can be embraced
by pluralism make no universalising, fundamentalist or triumphalist
claims (apart from their insistence on the universality of the core);
indeed they may severally welcome the existence of the alternative
conceptions with which they coexist. But universalist religions,
however
tolerant they may decide to be at a practical level, require other such
religious outlooks to be regarded as competitors for acceptance as
guides to the unique truth. Religion is
therefore not a coherent vehicle of cultural
identity in a self-consciously pluralistic world.[2]
Cultural identity and
multiculturalism
If it is true that cultural identity is one of
the most basic human needs, that without a sense of belonging to a
group
a man’s identity is impoverished, certain questions arise about the
nature of cultural wholes, and the way they interact and alter. These
problems are more acute if a culture is seen as holistic, in the sense
that its integrity is damaged if any part of it is lost or damaged or
altered. Such a view, of course, would in any case be an idealisation
of
reality, since few cultures have ever been entirely hermetically
isolated from other cultures; but the advent of global cultural
intermingling makes it even more impossible to sustain. In an age of
multiculturalism – that is, the simultaneous presence of many cultures
in one geopolitical unit (which may be the whole world, if we allow for
the cultural globalisation induced by travel and the media) – what are
we to say about the effect on cultural identity of the resulting
admixture of cultural elements? Berlin believed that the dominant
culture should be protected from too much infiltration and alteration
by
minority cultures, lest it forfeit too much of the character that gives
it strength and confidence; enthusiastic multiculturalists may disagree.
Anti-monism
Monism has the potential to become the fifth
horseman of the apocalypse. The idea that
there is a single, universal set of moral rules,
applicable to everyone, at all times and in all climes, is, if one
tries to cash it out in specific terms, absurd. Any rules capable of
applying to Tobriand Islanders and New York executives, to primitive
hunter-gatherers and sophisticated intellectuals, would have to be so
general as to be virtually free of content. And there is also the
variety introduced by differences in taste, temperament, ability or
vocation: are all these to be eliminated in deference to some
universalising system of preferences among such properly unrankable
alternatives? If this is the claim of monism, true monism can scarcely
ever have been embraced by reasonable men; in this comprehensive sense,
there is no
need for exemplary monists such as Christians or Communists, Moslems or
Fascists, to be monist at all, for all these creeds must recognise the
differences between people, places and times. There may be ideologies
so
fierce that such variability is denied, but they are unlikely to win
sufficient credence to achieve a status beyond that of fringe,
extremist
cults. Surely the central characteristics of a monist outlook worth
serious consideration must be other than these. A plausible monism must
be distinguished from non-monist outlooks not by its failure to
recognise the kind of variety just alluded to, but by its insistence
that, given such variety, there is a single correct solution to any
moral problem that arises against this background. Circumstances alter
cases – all agree on that – but for the monist they do not alter the
principles according to which the correct way forward, in whatever
circumstances, is to be discovered.
It may seem that we have now returned to our starting-point: we began
by denying the plausibility of universal rules and ended up by
suggesting universal principles. The difference is this: the denied
rules were very specific injunctions for the guidance of everyday
conduct – for example, regulations about the proper disposal of dead
bodies – whereas the suggested principles are more procedural, more
sensitive to the differing cultural, historical or individual contexts
in which they may be applied – for example, the rule that the will of
God always trumps the inclinations of the individual. Monism is to be
rejected in either guise, but it is not fair to start with a conception
of monism so implausible that it is just a straw man.
Berlin and evil
One of the problems I see in
Berlin’s work is that there tends to be a pervasive if unspoken
assumption that people are benevolent – that they are acting for the
best according to their lights. They may sometimes be the victims of
quite appalling empirical error – Berlin often instanced the false
beliefs about Jews held by Nazis, beliefs which, had they been true,
might have justified their behaviour – but, once these errors are
cleared away, matters will improve. This may be so to some extent, but
it is surely a massive underestimation of human malevolence, of the
sheer nastiness and bloody-mindedness (to put it no more strongly) that
is lurking somewhere in most of us, and doing a great deal more than
lurk in many people known to us all. A picture of the moral nature of
mankind that does not allow for the force of evil, if one may use this
terminology, is unrealistic, and therefore flawed. The
empirically-minded observer must take the world as he finds it, not as
he would like it to be. Berlin himself was unusually sweet-natured and
benign, and this may be part of an explanation of why he gave so little
attention to aspects of human nature which were under-represented in
his own makeup.
Rough notes
2 reasons for clash of ideals: (1) they just do
clash anyway – even when viewed under the old system; (2) if created,
they are bound to, since unfettered creation follows no guidelines that
guarantee consistency among its results.
The nature of values: sui generis.
Non-core values: chosen from a pre-existing
selection, a bran-tub, or invented? Both? Is the core fixed or can it
grow (shrink?)? Is it, in fact, a universal feature of human moral
agreement that its boundaries will shift? This must be the hope of
those
who seek moral progress.[3]
Notes
[1] Some religions may not be
universalist, which makes them very paradoxical, given that the desire
for universally true transcendental guidelines might be thought to be
one of the most basic elements of men’s religious instincts; but that
is
a separate issue which can be left on one side for present purposes. [back]
[2] Cf. my ‘The Compatibility
of
Incompatibles’, Independent, 20 February 1993, 33. [back]
[3] Growth in the core leads to
alteration
of the horizon; growth in the periphery may alter the core and/or the
horizon; the common purpose of society is to eschew
the idea of a common purpose. [back]
© Henry Hardy 2004
|